IMPORTANT NOTE ON THESE DISCUSSION MATERIALS
The following are discussion materials assembled solely for deliberation by the President’s
Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States. Each set of discussion materials was
prepared by a working group for the Commission’s use in studying and deliberating on the
issues identified in Executive Order 14023 and is informed by the Commission’s public
deliberations on October 15, 2021.
These materials attempt to set forth the broad range of arguments that have been made in the
course of the public debate over reform of the Supreme Court. They were designed to be
inclusive in their discussion of these arguments to assist the Commission in robust, wide-ranging
deliberations.
The inclusion of particular arguments in these draft materials does not constitute a Commission
endorsement or rejection of any of them, and specific points of analysis or particular
perspectives appearing in the drafts should not be understood to reflect the Commission's views
or those of any particular Commissioner. Consistent with Executive Order 14023, the
Commission includes members with diverse perspectives on these issues. Commissioners
therefore can be expected to hold various and even strongly opposing views, which will be the
subject of deliberation at the public meeting scheduled for November 19, 2021.
Prior to its next public meeting, the Commission will post a draft final Report for deliberation
and a vote on its submission to the President.
1
CHAPTER 3: TERM LIMITS
Among the proposals for reforming the Supreme Court, non-renewable limited terms—or
“term limitsfor Supreme Court Justices have enjoyed considerable, bipartisan support.
Advocacy groups, nonprofits, and membership organizations have expressed their support for
term limits. In testimony before the Commission, a bipartisan group of experienced Supreme
Court practitioners concluded that an eighteen-year non-renewable term “warrants serious
consideration.”
1
Major think tanks and their leaders have also endorsed the concept,
2
as have
both liberal and conservative constitutional scholars.
3
When the National Constitution Center
organized separate groups of “conservative” scholars and “progressive” scholars to draft their
own proposals for improving the Constitution, both groups concluded that Supreme Court
Justices should be limited to eighteen-year terms.
4
Yet other scholars and commentators have
questioned the idea of altering the system of life tenure,
5
which has been in place since the
Constitution established the Supreme Court and the judicial power.
This Chapter considers the full range of debate over term limits. In addition, it addresses
numerous design questions policymakers would need to take into account when developing such
a system. Part I presents a series of arguments for term limits, explaining how term limits would
enable a regularized system of appointments to the Court that would preserve the value of
judicial independence, make it more likely all Justices will serve for roughly equal numbers of
years, and ensure that the Court’s membership would be broadly responsive to the outcome of
democratic elections over time. Part II then sets out a series of objections to term limits, focusing
on their possible harms to judicial independence and legitimacy. In Part III, we consider how to
design a constitutional amendment that would institute a system of term limits. In Part IV, we
consider whether and how Congress might achieve the equivalent through statute. In each of
these two Parts, we consider questions such as how long Supreme Court Justices’ terms should
be, how many appointments each President should be able to make in four years’ time, and how
to transition to a term-limited system. We conclude in Parts V and VI by addressing some
additional concerns: first, the potential impasse in the Senate’s confirmation process that would
stymie a new system of term limits; second, the possibility that adoption of term limits through
statute would invite further intervention in the judiciary by Congress.
I. The Justifications for Term Limits
U.S. Supreme Court Justices have always had life tenure. But as proponents of term
limits point out, defined terms for high court justices are in fact commonplace at the state level.
Since the Founding, states have decidedly moved away from life-tenure for justices of their
highest courts. Today almost all states impose term limits on the justices of their highest courts,
with terms ranging from six to fifteen years. Terms are renewable through elections in many
states, though the majority of states impose a mandatory retirement age. Three of the four states
that do not have term limits impose mandatory retirement. Thirty-one states and the District of
Columbia have some form of mandatory retirement,
6
with the majority of states setting the
retirement age at 70.
7
Rhode Island is the only state that currently has neither term limits nor a
mandatory retirement age for its supreme court justices.
8
2
The United States is the only major constitutional democracy in the world that has neither
a retirement age nor a fixed term limit for its high court Justices.
9
Among the world’s
democracies, at least 27 have term limits for their constitutional courts. And those that do not
have term limits, such as the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom, typically impose age
limits.
10
In light of this contrast, one scholar who testified before the Commission opined that,
“were we writing the United States Constitution anew, there is no way we would adopt the
particular institutional structure that we have for judicial tenure. No other country has true
lifetime tenure for its justices, and for good reason.”
11
In the view of proponents of term limits, the existing system lacks adequate justification
beyond the fact that it has always been in place. Currently, the number of appointments available
to a President can vary greatly because of random chance; when a vacancy arises depends on
when Justices leave the bench due to illness or death, or when they themselves choose to retire.
As elaborated in more detail below, some Presidents are able to make three (or more)
appointments in a term while others make none. These differences in opportunities, term limits
proponents argue, serve no obvious structural purpose.
Proponents of term limits argue that regularizing the appointments process would address
these arbitrary consequences of life tenure by making judicial appointments more predictable and
the composition of the U.S. Supreme Court more rationally related to the outcome of democratic
elections over time. Proposals for staggered eighteen-year terms, for example, discussed in detail
in Parts III and IV, would ensure that all Presidents have the opportunity to appoint two Justices
to the Supreme Court in each term they serve. This predictability, proponents argue, would strike
a more appropriate balance than the current system between two important features of our
constitutional system of checks and balances: judicial independence on the one hand and long-
term responsiveness of the judiciary to our democratic system of representation on the other.
By providing for tenure during “good Behaviour,” Article III of the Constitution provides
judges with independence from direct and inappropriate external pressures and political
influence when they interpret laws, review executive actions and administrative regulations, and
consider the constitutionality of state and federal legislation.
12
Article II of the Constitution
authorizes the elected branches to affect the composition of the judiciary through appointments
over time; the Constitution gives the President and Senate power over appointments to the
federal judiciary, and it gives Congress power over the structure and jurisdiction of the federal
courts. Proponents of term limits emphasize that the influence of elections on the composition of
the Court and its work is thus indirect, but that it is nevertheless an important element of the
constitutional system. From the perspective of those who urge term limits, these various
provisions of the Constitution aim to make the individual members of the judiciary independent
at any given point in time, but the composition of the judiciary as a whole responsive over time
to the people’s will, as expressed through its electoral decisions about who occupies the
presidency and the Senate.
Proponents of term limits contend that the reform would better strike this balance than the
current system in two respects. Long fixed terms, such as terms of eighteen years, coupled with
post-service guarantees of financial security, would insulate individual Justices from political
3
pressure and financial temptation and function as effectively as life tenure to safeguard judicial
independence. At the same time, such fixed terms reflect the idea that democratic majorities, as
reflected in who is elected to the presidency and the Senate, should have the same or a roughly
equal opportunity to influence who sits on the Supreme Court through new nominations—an
objective that is poorly served by the current system of life tenure. Relatedly, proponents stress,
lifetime tenure does not comport with the ideal of limited government authority. The nine
individuals who sit on the Supreme Court wield extraordinary power over critical social and
political questions, often for several decades. Though judicial independence requires them to be
insulated from the same forms of accountability imposed on the political branches, life tenure
arguably arrogates too much power to single individuals.
Proponents of term limits caution that one should not confuse the argument that the
Court’s composition should reflect electoral outcomes over time with a claim that Presidents
have a right to make the Supreme Court generate a particular set of results. In our constitutional
system, judges and Justices are not and should not be considered the mere representatives of
political parties or the creatures of a particular President, and the argument for term limits does
not rest on such assumptions. Moreover, Presidents may appoint Justices for many reasons other
than the hope or expectation that the Justice will support the President’s particular policy agenda
or constitutional philosophy. Presidents may wish to achieve geographic or demographic
diversity on the Court, attract new voters through the selection of a nominee, or choose a Justice
with a particular set of professional experiences. And history shows that Presidents cannot
necessarily predict the path a Justice will pursue; Justices often confront new issues in contexts
quite different from the circumstances in which they were appointed. Thus, the argument for
regularized appointments is not an argument for making Justices the representatives of Presidents
or a particular ideology. Rather, according to proponents, the ability of Presidents to nominate
Justices at regular intervals that would be afforded by term limits, coupled with the Senate’s
authority to advise and consent, would help ensure, at least in the long run, that the Supreme
Court does not fall too far out of line with the country’s evolving norms and political values.
Proponents of term limits underscore that their value in advancing these constitutional
principles is heightened by various ways in which the consequences of life tenure have changed
over time. In particular, the average length of Justices’ terms has expanded.
13
Life spans have
lengthened and modern Justices may increasingly delay retirement.
14
Up until the late 1960s the
average term of service was around fifteen years. By contrast, the average tenure of the Justices
who have left the Court since 1970 has been roughly twenty-six years.
15
In the future, it’s quite
possible that tenure will continue to lengthen, as several recent Justices have been younger than
their predecessors and life spans generally continue to grow. The increasing length of the
Justices’ terms, in turn, raises the stakes of each nomination. Political partisans may press for
nominating younger candidates in the hope that they will serve longer
16
and thus allow for the
entrenchment of particular views on the Court for three or more decades into the future.
Proponents also note that the variation in the number of each President’s opportunities to
nominate a Justice has become more pronounced. Throughout history, the median, modal, and
mean number of chances for a Supreme Court appointment has been approximately two per four-
year term.
17
Most Presidents have had either one or two opportunities, and a small number have
been very lucky and received four or more. But sometimes Presidents get none at all. This
4
situation has occurred more frequently since the mid 1970s. In the 188 years from the presidency
of George Washington to the presidency of Gerald Ford, there were only five presidential terms
out of forty-seven (just eleven percent) in which Presidents did not get an opportunity to make a
Supreme Court appointment.
18
But in the forty-four years from Jimmy Carter to Donald Trump,
Presidents did not make a single appointment in three out of eleven terms (twenty-seven
percent)—and four out of eleven terms if we include Republicans’ refusal to consider the
nomination of Judge Merrick Garland during President Barack Obama’s second term.
Again, proponents of term limits do not seek partisan balance. If a party wins the White
House more often, its Presidents should have the opportunity to nominate more Justices, though
this opportunity may be checked, as with all judicial appointments, by the Senate’s advice and
consent. But, proponents emphasize, our current system allows parties to shape the composition
and influence the direction of the Court to a degree that does not necessarily reflect their record
of electoral success over time.
19
They argue that the existing system—buffeted by chance illness
or deaths, possible strategic behavior, and aggressive political tacticsmakes it easier than it
should be for parties that lose elections to nevertheless have outsized impact on who sits on the
Court and on its general direction.
Indeed, another justification offered for term limits is that they would largely eliminate
the possibility of “strategic retirements” and, just as importantly, the perception that Justices
retire for strategic reasons. Through strategic retirements, Justices attempt to control the future
direction of the Court by creating Supreme Court openings when there is a particular President or
Senate majority. Conversely, Justices may remain on the Court, even if they are no longer up to
the job, because they are waiting for a different President to select their replacement on the
Court. This kind of strategic calculation, or the perception of it, can fuel public beliefs that the
Court is a partisan institution. It can contribute to the perception that the system is unfair or
rigged, in part because strategic retirements prevent Presidents from receiving a roughly equal
number of appointments for each term in office. Moreover, the possibility that Justices might
retire strategically can lead to public relations campaigns to push a Justice to retire precisely so
that a particular President can appoint a successor. Though it is impossible to know why any
particular Justice chooses to retire at a particular moment, term limits would put a stop to both
the possibility and perception of strategic retirements. Under one possible design of term limits
that we discuss further below, Presidents (with Senate advice and consent) would only be able to
fill out the remaining years of the term for a retiring Justice, eliminating much of the advantage
of, and hence the motivation for, retiring strategically. Their proponents do not claim that term
limits are a panacea for polarization, nor that they would stop political parties from fighting over
judicial appointments. But by regularizing Supreme Court appointments, term limits would make
the system of Supreme Court appointments fairer, less arbitrary, and more predictable, and
therefore enhance the Court’s legitimacy in the eyes of the public.
Finally, in addition to these arguments based in constitutional structure and principle,
proponents of term limits also believe that they would enhance the Court’s decisionmaking, on
the ground that a regular rotation in personnel tends to improve the quality of decisionmaking
over time.
20
Judges, like others, are inevitably a product of their time. After distinguished
professional careers and eighteen-year terms on the Court, judges may tend to grow more distant
from the experiences and contexts to which their legal decisions apply. Judges, like others, can
5
also become set in their ways, making fresh perspectives on issues more difficult to achieve.
Rotation in office introduces new voices and new interpersonal dynamics into the deliberations
of multimember bodies, as well as more generational diversity, which may bring valuable
perspectives.
21
Given how powerful the Court has become as an institution—certainly more
powerful than the framers of our Constitution expected—relying on Justices to voluntarily make
way for younger figures who can help revitalize the Court is asking a great deal. These are some
of the reasons that rules and norms governing the leadership of other organizations often require
a change of leadership after many years.
22
These are also some of the reasons that other systems
that appoint judges through non-political mechanisms, such as through committees of judges and
lawyers, nonetheless impose either term limits or mandatory retirement ages on their judges.
23
The possibility of imposing a mandatory retirement age on Justices is sometimes offered
as an alternative to term limits, and the Commission heard testimony on this possibility.
24
Mandatory retirements would arguably improve the quality of decisionmaking for the reasons
stated above and provide some degree of responsiveness to elections over time, while preserving
judicial independence by allowing for long terms. As with term limits, a mandatory retirement
age would make it possible to know when a given Justice will retire (assuming that the Justice
does not die or leave the bench early). But, according to term limit proponents, a mandatory
retirement age is inferior to term limits in important respects. It would not guarantee regular
appointments. It would still encourage parties to nominate ever younger candidates in order to
squeeze the maximum number of years out of each appointment. Thus, if the goal is to regularize
appointments and to ensure that political parties that win elections get a predictable number of
opportunities to appoint new Justices, term limits offer a better option.
II. Objections to Term Limits
The Commission also heard and considered arguments against term limits. In the main,
the opponents argue that the current system of appointing and protecting the independence and
neutrality of federal judges and Justices, through life tenure, has worked well for over 230 years.
The independent federal judiciary, protected by lifetime tenure, is one of the most signal
accomplishments of our constitutional system. Opponents argue that term limit proponents
therefore have a heavy burden of persuasion when they seek to remove an important pillar
provided by the Constitution to uphold judicial independence. Opponents contend that far from
meeting this high bar, term limits are as likely to worsen existing problems, such as the
partisanship of the confirmation process, while at the same time introducing new problems.
Most fundamentally, term limit opponents deny one of the premises embraced by
proponents: that it would be good for Presidents each to receive two appointments to the Court in
order to make it more responsive to the people. According to opponents, it is decidedly not the
role of a judge to decide cases according to the judge’s estimation of the temper of the times,
except in the rare instance where the law requires consideration of contemporary mores in a
particular context. Rather, say the opponents, it is the role of a judge to apply and develop the
law, using the tools of judging emblematic of the centuries-old common law tradition, relying on
precedents, text, factual context, and the purposes of the law.
6
Similarly, opponents regard the term limit proposal as reflecting the underlying but mistaken
belief that judges are political actors, even political partisans (although they recognize that term
limit proponents disclaim this view). The opponents contend that a judge who acts as a partisan
or for political purposes acts in violation of the judicial oath (“that I will administer justice
without respect to persons, and do equal right to the poor and to the rich, and that I will faithfully
and impartially discharge and perform all the duties incumbent upon me”). To the extent that
term limits can be perceived as founded on that acceptance, the opponents of term limits believe
that inestimable damage could be done to the federal courts by adopting term limits.
Opponents also raise a number of more specific objections to the term limit proposal and
its justifications, objections that emanate from these concerns about politicizing the Court.
First, opponents see term limits as setting up a dynamic in which the presidential election
focuses not just on Court appointments in general but on the two guaranteed vacancies and
appointments specifically. If two seats on the Supreme Court are guaranteed to open every four
years, the Court might become even more of an issue in electoral politics than it currently is.
Presidential candidates might have even greater incentives to make promises about whom they
will appoint, and presidential elections might increasingly appear to the public to also be
elections of specific identified persons—now candidates—to the Supreme Court. In a highly
polarized environment, it might be especially harmful to reinforce connections between the
Court and presidential politics. Such an electoral process might change not just the public’s
perception of the Court, but also how the Justices view themselves and behave, making the
institution more partisan. Moreover, introducing term limits might reinforce the erroneous
message that appointments to the Supreme Court are the spoils of politics or the property of a
particular President or party. Relatedly, one critic of term limits worries that the Justices “will be
Republican appointees or Democratic appointees in a more explicit sense than they are now,”
and that some Justices “may . . . view their own roles in a manner a little more political and a
little less law-like.”
25
Second, opponents of term limits point out that if one of the failings of the current system
is a bitterly partisan confirmation process, then prescribing yet more regular confirmation
hearings, as term limits does, simply worsens an already bad situation. While there is sometimes
the suggestion that eighteen-year terms might engender less partisanship than lifetime
appointments, opponents of term limits think a reduction of such partisanship in the United
States is unlikely given the underlying dynamics of the current confirmation process and the
behavior of interest groups.
26
Third, some commentators and scholars have also expressed concern that term limits
(whether through constitutional amendment or by statute) would threaten the basic structural
principle of judicial independence.
27
They argue that life tenure is essential to that independence,
as evidenced in our long-standing historical practice. Opponents are not comforted by citations to
foreign courts, or to the state supreme courts where justices are often elected, sometimes in
partisan elections, and where term limits are part of the retention and reappointment election
process. Opponents note that it is perilous to draw conclusions from systems that are so
fundamentally different.
7
Opponents of term limits also believe that judicial independence could be compromised
by Justices having to consider what they would do after their terms expire; their plans for the
future might affect either their performance as Justices or public perceptions of that performance.
One might worry that a Justice who is eying future positions in government might try to curry
favor with political constituencies, or that a Justice who is eyeing future positions in industry or
at a law firm might decide cases in light of those plans. While it might be thought that term limits
reduce the pressure for Presidents to appoint younger people, such that most Justices who serve
eighteen-year terms may still view their positions on the Court as their last major position, other
Justices who have served some portion of the eighteen-year term might decide that they would
prefer to take a different unlimited position in government or the private sector rather than filling
out the rest of the term. In order to address this problem, term limits proposals would have to be
coupled with troubling restrictions on post-Court employment. But, critics contend, this solution
is not likely to draw universal support, raises questions of enforcement, and constitutes a
questionable restriction on any American’s future employment while ignoring our history in
which admired Justices have left the Court after sometimes short periods of time to serve in the
government or run for President.
28
Fourth, by design, term limits would produce more turnover on the Supreme Court than
has been typical in recent decades. This turnover could have costs as well as benefits. At the
outset, one might object that term limits would deprive the Court of certain benefits that can
result from Justices serving for several decades. Some might believe life tenure tends to improve
the judgment of the Justices because wisdom comes with age and experience. Moreover, several
of the greatest Justices in American historyChief Justice Marshall comes quickly to mind
served on the Court for a very long time (though some of the Court’s most notorious Justices did
so as well). A system of term limits would make such distinguished careers impossibleor at
least shorterin the future and might reduce the stature of the Court as a whole, including its
stature with the public, the bar, and the lower courts. Moreover, the question of the advanced age
of long-serving Justices ignores, in the view of critics, that this feature never defines splits on the
Court; the most pronounced divisions are not by age, but by ideology.
Another concern about increased turnover is that it might destabilize the Court’s doctrine.
To the extent that new Justices have different views of the law than their predecessors, and to the
extent that they are willing to overrule or narrow precedents with which they disagree, more
turnover on the Supreme Court could lead to more frequent doctrinal shifts, or even cycles in
which major precedents are discarded only to be reinstated later, perhaps in very short order. To
opponents of term limits, the current system provides sufficient turnover and there is little reason
to adopt a new and untried system simply to generate more turnover.
29
Fifth, those who object to term limits fear that they would give the President too much
power, an especially worrying concern given how powerful the modern presidency has become.
If Presidents make new appointments to the Supreme Court every two years, two-term Presidents
will have appointed four of the nine active Justices by the final year of their administrations. The
power to appoint four-ninths of the Supreme Court is a substantial power; term limits would lock
in that power and make it less subject to the vagaries of chance.
30
Critics might therefore argue
that the randomness of presidential opportunities to make Supreme Court appointments
throughout history has actually been an advantage, because it limits presidential power and
8
ambitions, and thereby helps preserve the Court’s independence. And over time, opponents
argue, we might expect a “balancing out,” such that the randomness of appointments over more
limited periods is not a sufficient source of concern to justify the institution of a system of limits.
Opponents also argue that a focus on the presidency and presidential politics in structuring
regularized appointments mistakenly minimizes the role of the Senate.
Sixth, a different type of objection involves the incentives for gamesmanship in particular
cases. If it is known that a swing Justice will lose the power to participate in cases on a specific
date, either litigants or lower-court judges might try to time a case accordingly.
31
Conversely,
Justices who want to weigh in on a question while they still have the power to do so might be
inclined to grant certiorari before the question has fully “percolate[d]” through the lower courts,
and they might also face temptations to accept cases that are not ideal “vehicle[s]” for presenting
and deciding the question.
32
Similarly, other Justices might vote to defer hearing a case or an
issue until their colleague had been forced to leave the Court.
* * *
Ultimately, opponents of term limits caution that any such proposal should not appear as
a settling of scores, as an attack on particular Justices, or an effort to change the substantive
opinions and direction of the current Court. And term limits by themselves cannot ensure that the
President will nominate high-quality individuals. Those who object to term limits believe that the
Supreme Court has functioned with life tenure ever since the Founding, and switching to a
system of term limits poses major design challenges and could have unintended consequences. A
broader concern they hold is less about term limits than about reform in general. In our current
polarized environment, any change to the structure of the Supreme Court might be regarded with
suspicion. In addition, one reform might open the door to further proposals for structural change,
with some risk to the stability of the institution.
Term limit proponents acknowledge that the risk of unintended consequences is an
important point to consider, but they argue that it is not a conclusive argument for inertia,
particularly because the status quo has significant problems. Indeed, they argue, inertia too can
have unintended consequences, as illustrated by the gradually lengthening tenure of justices over
time and the increased perception that Justices retire strategically. Responding to the costs and
risks asserted by opponents, they note that the average tenure of the Justices who left the
Supreme Court from the Founding until 1970 was less than eighteen years.
33
So, proponents
argue, the Court has historically experienced greater turnover than a system of eighteen-year
terms would be likely to produce now. They argue that concerns over judicial independence or
increased executive power are not supported by actual experience in state or foreign courts, nor
are they supported more generally by the empirical literature.
34
Moreover, these concerns can
and should be addressed in careful design of the system, such as long and nonrenewable term
limits, a guaranteed lifetime of judicial office and compensation while performing other judicial
duties, and the coupling of term limits with some restrictions on the types of post-Court
employment. Even some critics of term limits, they note, think it fair to expect that “long fixed
terms followed by assignment to a court of appeals” would give individual Justices a degree of
independence as it currently stands.
35
And they respond to opponents’ concerns about
9
politicization of the appointments process by pointing out that the process is already highly
politicized and that an eighteen-year term is long enough to avoid any increase in the heat of
confirmation battles.
III. Analyzing a Constitutional Amendment for Term Limits
This section identifies the major issues to consider in designing a system of term limits.
These issues include the size of the Court, the length of the Justices’ terms, how to fill vacancies
that arise before a set term ends, and how to transition from the current system.
Many of these issues arise under either a proposed constitutional amendment creating
term limits or a statutory term limit proposal. But the options for addressing them differ
depending on which path is being considered. In this Part, we discuss these issues in the context
of a constitutional amendment to adopt term limits. In Part IV, we do so in the context of a
statutory term limits proposal, and we also discuss whether these reforms would require
constitutional amendment or whether they could be enacted by Congress. While our aim is not to
recommend a specific proposal, we believe it is necessary to discuss plausible reform options in
order to ground our analysis.
A. Setting the Court’s Size and the Appropriate Term Length
A system of term limits ought to specify the appropriate size of the Court. One major
justification for a staggered, term-limited system of appointment is that such a system would
bring about less randomness and greater equality across presidential terms in the number of
Justices a President would have the opportunity to appoint. That aim would be drastically
undermined, however, were Congress free to vary the size of the Court. We separately evaluate
proposals to expand the size of the Court in Chapter 2 of this Report. For purposes of our
analysis here, we assume that an amendment would fix the Court’s size at nine Justices.
With a nine-member Court, the two likeliest options for term limits would be a twelve-
year term or an eighteen-year term, as both would create a roughly equal number of appointment
opportunities in each presidential term. In recent decades, the overwhelming majority of term
limit proposals have endorsed the eighteen-year version. In that version, each President would
have two regular appointments in a single presidential term. In the twelve-year version, each
President would have three such appointments.
Important trade-offs are involved in this choice. As we noted at the outset of this Chapter,
from the perspective of the state courts and international peers, an eighteen-year term is quite
long. Of the forty-seven states that impose term limits for their highest court judges, only one
state has a term longer than twelve years.
36
Similarly, of the twenty-seven countries that impose
a term limit, those limits range between five and fifteen years.
37
The German constitutional
court, considered one of the strongest constitutional courts in Europe, is composed of judges who
serve twelve-year non-renewable terms and who must retire at age sixty-eight.
38
10
As this experience in the states and other countries suggests, there is a case to be made
for twelve-year terms if the structure of the Court is considered in isolation from the larger
political circumstances of the appointments process. With twelve-year terms, each presidential
term would involve three regularly scheduled appointments. In addition, a President elected for
two terms would have the power to appoint six regularly appointed Justices. Even if a
constitutional amendment for term limits would to some extent reduce the intensity of political
conflict over Court appointments, three appointments every four years would put the Court at the
center of the political process on an almost yearly basis. There are also reasons to be concerned
that enabling a single two-term President to make six appointments gives one person too much
power to reshape the Court. This tradeoff has led most proponents of term limits in the United
States to endorse an eighteen-year term. For simplicity’s sake, and in the light of these
considerations, we will use an eighteen-year term limit to ground our analysis.
That said, circumstances could change, making potential turbulence less of a risk. If so,
the costs and benefits of a twelve-year term as opposed to an eighteen-year term might be
weighted differently than at present. For this reason, the designers of a constitutional amendment
might consider whether the amendment should give Congress the power to adopt prospectively a
twelve-year term (that is, to adopt a statute that would take effect for Justices appointed after the
date of enactment). Drafters should take care to hew to the core purpose of such an amendment
by ensuring that each President receives the same number of regularly scheduled appointments.
B. Effective Date and Timing of Appointments
The designers of a constitutional amendment to implement a term limit system must make
several choices related to the timing of the reform.
First, drafters must decide when the amendment would take effect. The amendment
could, of course, take effect upon adoption. If there is concern that knowledge of who the sitting
President is at the time the amendment takes effect would make it more difficult for the
amendment to be adopted, the amendment could be structured to take effect starting at some later
date. For instance, it could begin in the first presidential administration elected after the
amendment is approved.
Second, drafters must also determine the timing of appointments. The amendment could
specify when during a presidential term the President’s two appointments would arise. If the
drafters wished to avoid appointments arising during an election year, they could specify that
appointments would arise in years one and three of a presidential term. To avoid disrupting an
ongoing Supreme Court term, the amendment could specify that the outgoing Justice’s term ends
on a specific date that typically falls after the Court has issued all its opinions in argued cases.
The incoming Justice’s term can be made to run from that date, in which case Justices might
serve slightly fewer than eighteen years, given the time it would take for confirmation.
Third, drafters must also address how to fill seats that become vacant due to retirement,
death, or impeachment before the end of a Justice’s eighteen-year term. Once every Justice has
11
been appointed to an eighteen-year seat, this situation is not likely to occur often. Only one
Justice appointed in the last fifty years has served fewer than eighteen years.
39
We identify three options for how to fill seats that become vacant:
The first is to leave those seats unfilled for the remainder of any retiring Justice’s term,
thereby preventing any President from having more than two appointments in a presidential term.
That option would leave the Court to function without a full complement of Justices for what
might be extended periods; it would also mean the Court would likely have to function for
periods with an even number of Justices. The Court has functioned occasionally with an even
number of Justices, as it did for fourteen months after Justice Scalia’s death. Some argue that an
even-numbered Court encourages the Justices to deliberate more to find common ground, in an
effort to avoid leaving the Court unable to decide a case. In addition, the Court would not be able
to find state or national action unconstitutional absent greater consensus than a five-to-four
decision entails. But a significant cost of having an evenly divided Court is that it could prevent
the Court from ensuring that federal law is uniform throughout the country. If the courts of
appeals are divided on an issue, for example, there would be no higher judicial authority to
resolve that difference if the Court itself is evenly divided on the issue. The same law could be
held constitutional in one part of the country and unconstitutional in another.
A second option is that the sitting President, with Senate confirmation, would have the
power to appoint a candidate to fill out only the remainder of the original eighteen-year term.
Some witnesses testified that confirmation in this context should require a supermajority Senate
vote.
40
The justification for that higher hurdle is that seats that become vacant before the end of
an eighteen-year term reintroduce a random element into the timing of appointments by allowing
certain Presidents to make more than two appointments. On this view, those appointments should
succeed only if they are backed by a significant consensus in the Senate. Although a
supermajority requirement might lead some seats to remain vacant (as in the first option), no
President would be deprived of the right to make two regularly scheduled appointments in a
presidential term. If the amendment does permit the President to fill out the term of seats that
become vacant prematurely, the drafters might consider prohibiting the person appointed from
being reappointed to a full eighteen-year term.
A third option depends on how the amendment treats Justices who have reached the end
of their eighteen-year terms. The amendment might define these individuals as “Senior Justices,”
who continue to hold offices as Article III judges but no longer participate in the day-to-day
operation of the Court. Given that these Justices have all been confirmed by the Senate, the
amendment could give the President the option to designate a Senior Justice, if one is available,
to fill out an eighteen-year term that has become vacant prematurely. If unilateral presidential
designation is undesirable, the amendment could instead require the Senate to confirm the
President’s choice (if no Senior Justices are available, one of the first two options would have to
apply).
C. Designing the Transition to Fixed-Term Appointments
12
How to structure the Court’s transition to fixed-term appointments presents significant
practical challenges. The most significant options that have been proposed are discussed below.
For purposes of this analysis, our discussion will assume an eighteen-year term with regular
presidential nominations in years one and three of a President’s term.
1. Sitting Justices Retire on a Fixed Schedule That the Amendment Establishes
Under this approach, once the amendment takes effect, the longest-serving Justice would
retire in year one of the first presidential term in which the amendment takes effect. The next
most senior Justice would retire in year three, and so on. This strategy is the conceptually
cleanest structure for the transition. Were this approach adopted, sixteen years after the first
Justice is appointed to a term-limited seat, the full Court would consist entirely of Justices
serving eighteen-year terms. For instance, if the amendment took effect in 2025, the most junior
Justice on the current Court would retire in 2041, after twenty-one years of service. If this were
done through a constitutional amendment, the Commission does not perceive there to be any
significant constitutional issues in applying the amendment to sitting Justices.
2. Sitting Justices Remain on the Court as New Term-Limited Justices Are
Appointed
The Commission is aware that while the simplest approach would be to apply a term
limits amendment to the sitting Justices, this strategy might generate political conflict that would
make passage of an amendment difficult.
If the amendment is designed not to apply to currently sitting Justices, the Court could
expand temporarily. New Justices would start being appointed every two years for eighteen-year
terms after the amendment’s effective date. As legacy Justices leave, their seats would not be
filled as long as at least nine Justices would remain on the Court. It is likely that the Court would
never drop below nine Justices. One study concludes that, under this approach, it would take
around thirty-five years until the full Court consisted entirely of Justices serving for fixed
terms.
41
This approach does come with potential costs, however. It would likely produce a
considerably expanded Court for a period of years. In Chapter 2, we consider some of the
consequences of a larger bench, including that it could hamper the Court’s decisionmaking
(depending on how large the expansion is). That said, many of the highest courts in other
democracies have eleven or more members, and in many cases they function effectively by
sitting in panels, a prospect we also explore in Chapter 2.
42
On the other hand, no state supreme
court has more than nine judges and only seven are even that large; most have seven judges and
seventeen have five.
43
As one former federal judge testified to the Commission, above a certain
size, effective collective deliberation becomes more difficult.
44
In addition, in some years, the
Court might also have an even number of Justices, which would raise the issues discussed above
about the pros and cons of an even-numbered Court.
45
It is also uncertain how the public would
perceive the Court if its size fluctuated from year to year for many years. Closely divided
decisions on a Court that sometimes has nine members, sometimes eleven, sometimes thirteen,
13
might make the Court appear less stable and generate perceptions that outcomes turn on the
fortuity of how many Justices happen to be on the Court at any particular moment.
3. New Term-Limited Justices Are Appointed Only When Currently Sitting
Justices Vacate Their Seats
Another alternative proposed in academic work on this issue is that current Justices
continue to serve for life and new appointments are made only when the seat of a currently
sitting Justice becomes vacant.
46
The amendment would still establish a schedule of regular
eighteen-year appointments, into which retirements of currently sitting Justices would then have
to be integrated. For example, if a currently sitting Justice retires before the date for vacating that
seat occurs, the President nominates a Justice who would serve the next eighteen-year slot that is
scheduled to become available. Suppose under the amendment the first three eighteen-year terms
would arise in 2025, 2027, and 2029. If a currently sitting Justice leaves the bench in 2024, the
President would nominate a Justice whose term would be nineteen years (2024-2025 plus the
eighteen-year term that begins in 2025). If the next sitting Justice leaves in 2025, the President
would nominate a Justice whose term would be twenty years (2025-2027 plus the eighteen-year
term that begins in 2027). If another seat does not open up until 2031, the President would
nominate a Justice who would serve for only sixteen years (filling the term that was scheduled to
begin in 2029 and end in 2047).
This proposal would avoid temporary expansion of the Court, but it would also generate
the longest time interval before the full Court was composed of Justices serving eighteen-year
terms. One major study estimates that, under this proposal, it might take around fifty-two years
before the Court reached the point that all Justices were serving eighteen-year terms.
47
The
additional complexities just noted about timing of appointments might also be considered a cost
of this proposal.
4. Addressing Seats Held by Currently Sitting Justices That Become Vacated
Prematurely
If the amendment applies to currently sitting Justices, as in the first option above, a
distinct issue arises concerning seats of those Justices that might become vacant prematurely. For
example, a currently sitting Justice whose term would be scheduled to end in 2033 might vacate
the seat in 2025. This may be a more likely scenario than that a new Justice appointed to an
eighteen-year term would vacate that seat prematurely. Simply for reasons of age, it seems more
likely that a Justice on the current Court would leave office eight years before a scheduled end-
of-term date than would a newly appointed eighteen-year term Justice.
One option is the same as discussed earlier: the seat could remain vacant. But in this
context, that could leave the Court with fewer than nine Justices, and possibly an even number of
Justices, for an extended timeeight years, in the example above.
If the seat that becomes vacant is the next one the sitting President would be entitled to
fill in any event during the four-year term, the President could be given the power to nominate
the Justice to fill that seat. That Justice would then serve eighteen years plus the small amount of
14
additional time involved; if a currently sitting Justice’s term is scheduled to end in 2027, but
ends in 2026, the new Justice would serve one year plus the new eighteen-year term. Given that a
new Justice under this scenario would never serve more than twenty years, the normal
presidential nomination and Senate confirmation process might be appropriate (that is, without a
supermajority requirement).
If the President has not yet filled any of the two allocated seats, and the Justice who
leaves is the one whose term would expire in year three of the administration, there are two
options for addressing that scenario. In the first, the amendment would treat this situation as if
the President is filling the first of two seats. The Justice who would otherwise be scheduled to
retire first during that term would instead stay on until the term ends of the Justice scheduled to
retire in year three—the Justice who has left prematurely. At that point, that Justice retires and
the President fills the second seat. The second option is that the President appoints a Justice to
fill out the remainder of the term for the Justice who left early plus eighteen years. When the
term of the Justice scheduled to retire in year one of the administration ends, the President fills
that term as well. The first option reduces possibilities of strategic retirements, but might be
considered overly complex.
In any other context, the current President should at most have the authority to appoint a
replacement only for the rest of the term that the departing Justice was scheduled to serve. Under
the theory behind the term limits amendment, no President should get to make more than two
eighteen-year appointments in any single presidential term. With respect to the replacement
Justice, moreover, the options discussed earlier might be appropriate. First, a supermajority vote
requirement in the Senate might be appropriate. Second, if there are “senior” Supreme Court
Justices, one could be designated to serve out the remainder of the scheduled term.
D. Constraints on Justices Who Have Fully Retired After Finishing Their Term of
Service
Many countries that impose term limits or retirement ages on judges of their highest
courts also impose constraints on the post-service activities of those judges. There are two main
reasons for imposing such constraints. The most important is to avoid undermining the fact and
appearance of judicial independence by eliminating the likelihood of Justices’ altering their
behavior in their last years of their service on the Court to enhance certain post-service
employment opportunities. In addition, certain post-service positions might be detrimental to the
public’s sense of the integrity and professionalism of the Court. At the same time, it is important
that former Justices who choose to retire from judicial service altogether after their term ends
have appropriate opportunities to pursue other professional interests.
In order to address these concerns, the amendment could specify that at the end of their
service, Justices have the option of retaining the office of an Article III judge and remaining
available to serve by designation on any of the lower federal courts; to serve by designation on
the Supreme Court if a Justice in an eighteen-year seat vacates that seat prematurely; or to
perform other federal judicial functions. The amendment could also specify that upon completion
of their terms, Justices would continue to receive a pension for life commensurate with their
15
salaries on the bench.
48
But these two provisions would not solve the problem fully. With term
limits, some Justices would complete service at younger ages than the current average age at
which Justices leave the Court. Some will prefer to relinquish their Article III commission and
work in other capacities.
Former Justices who have chosen to retire fully from the bench could be barred from
certain kinds of employment for a certain period of time. The prospect of high-level government
employment is a particular concern, given the risk of public perceptions that a Justice will have
ruled in certain ways late in their term to curry favor with the sitting government. Retired
Justices could be prohibited from involvement in legal matters that had been the subject of
proceedings before the Court and, perhaps, closely related matters.
49
Former Justices could also
be barred from working on any matters before the Court. Service in roles such as mediator,
arbitrator, or law school lecturer, on the other hand, are most compatible with the role of a retired
Justice. While some of these concerns should be addressed in any constitutional amendment—
such as whether term-limited Justices retain the option of remaining Article III judges—others
might be appropriately handled through legislation.
IV. Enacting Term Limits through Statute
Members of the Commission are divided about whether Congress has the power under
the Constitution to create the equivalent of term limits by statute. Some believe that a statutory
solution is within Congress’s powers. Others believe that no statutory solution is constitutional,
or that any statute would raise so many difficult constitutional and implementation questions that
it would be unwise to proceed through statute. Opponents of term limits cite these complexities
as reasons to eschew term limits altogether.
In this Part, we consider the primary statutory approach and two alternative approaches.
In all three proposals, Presidents appoint new Justices in the first and third years of their terms in
office. As noted in the introduction to this Chapter, we focus on these proposals to ground our
analysis rather than to endorse these proposals over all others. In addition, because the
Commissioners are divided as to whether it would be constitutional to implement term limits via
statute, we offer what we take to be the best argument for each position but do not seek to
resolve the matter. We also examine some of the prudential concerns arising from these
proposals. If Congress were contemplating imposing term limits by statute, a constitutional
amendment that simply specified the size of the Court might still be advisable, for the reasons
discussed above.
The main focus of our analysis is the so-called Junior/Senior Justice proposal. It creates
the functional equivalent of term limits by providing that, after eighteen years of service, Justices
become Senior Justices and stop participating in the ordinary work of the Court. This proposal
features elements common to other proposals that scholars and advocates have offered,
50
and the
constitutional issues we discuss here are also common to those proposals. The two alternative
solutions—the Original/Appellate Jurisdiction proposal and the Designated Justices proposal—
16
attempt to address potential constitutional problems with the Junior/Senior Justice proposal, but
they raise their own sets of constitutional issues.
In all three proposals, Justices would spend an eighteen-year nonrenewable term
participating in the ordinary work of the Supreme Court. After that period, they would perform a
different or a subsidiary set of duties.
A. The Junior and Senior Justices Proposal
In the Junior/Senior Justice proposal, Congress passes a statute that provides that, after
eighteen years of service as a “Junior Justice” deciding cases, each Justice would assume senior
status. Thereafter, these “Senior Justices” would no longer participate regularly in the ordinary
work of the Court. But they would perform other duties, including sitting by designation in the
lower federal courts and assisting the Chief Justice with administrative duties. Congress could
specify these duties by statute, or it could leave it to the Justices themselves to decide on them
through an internal rule.
51
If the duties of Senior Justices were not sufficiently germane to the office of a Supreme
Court Justice, the change in duties might amount to appointment to a new office. This would
require a new nomination by the President and confirmation by the Senate. However, it is not
clear that the germaneness requirement applies to the prospective redefinition of an office. In any
case, the Supreme Court’s understanding of germaneness appears to be very broad. In Weiss v.
United States,
52
for example, the Court held that the duties of a military judge were sufficiently
germane to the duties of a commissioned officer that the officer could be designated to serve as a
judge without going through the appointments process.
The Justices already perform the duties listed above and that would pertain to Senior
Justices under the proposal. Current federal law authorizes Justices to sit on circuit courts.
53
And
as a historical matter, federal law long required the Justices to sit on other federal courts in
addition to hearing cases on the Supreme Court. For almost all of the first hundred years of the
Republic, Supreme Court Justices “rode circuit”: they heard and decided cases in the lower
federal courts. With the Judiciary Act of 1801, Congress abolished circuit riding, only to
reinstate it in the Repeal Act of 1802 after control of Congress changed hands. The Supreme
Court rejected a constitutional challenge to the 1802 Act in Stuart v. Laird,
54
in which the
challenger sought to reverse a circuit court’s judgment partly on the ground that “the judges of
the supreme court have no right to sit as circuit judges, not being appointed as such.”
55
The
Supreme Court responded that circuit riding was so well established that its validity was no
longer open to question:[P]ractice and acquiescence under it for a period of several years,
commencing with the organization of the judicial system, affords an irresistible answer, and has
indeed fixed the construction.”
56
Justices continued to have circuit-riding duties until the late
nineteenth century.
57
Existing practice and precedent offer a model for the types of duties Senior Justices might
perform. 28 U.S.C. § 371 provides two options for federal judges, including Supreme Court
Justices, who meet certain service and age requirements. They may “retire from the office” under
§ 371(a), at which point they no longer hold the office of federal judge or Justice but continue to
17
receive an annuity equivalent to their salary at the time of retirement. Or they may “retain the
office but retire from regular active service” under § 371(b) and “continue to receive the salary
of the office” if they perform a different set of duties, which they may select from a list set out in
later sections. Listed duties include “a caseload involving courtroom participation,” “substantial
judicial duties not involving courtroom participation,” “substantial administrative duties directly
related to the operation of the courts,” or “substantial duties for a Federal or State governmental
entity.” For lower court judges, the status created in § 371(b) is usually called senior status.
Under the current rules, judges who take senior status need not sit on any cases at all.
They may, however, sit by designation within their own circuit at the discretion of the chief
judge or judicial council of their circuit. They may also sit by designation in other circuits at the
discretion of the Chief Justice upon presentation of a certificate of necessity by the chief judge or
circuit justice of the other circuit. Supreme Court Justices who retire from regular active service
(and take the analogue of senior status for lower court judges) are not allowed to participate in
any decisions or actions of the Supreme Court, but they may sit by designation in the lower
federal courts.
58
As with a constitutional amendment, drafters of a Junior/Senior Justice statute would
have to make decisions about whether it would apply to sitting Justices, when the appointments
of term-limited Justices would begin, how to handle vacancies that arose outside of the
scheduled process, and whether there should be restrictions on the future employment of former
Justices. The discussion of these issues in the constitutional amendment section applies equally
to such a statute, with the caveat that applying the statute to sitting Justices might raise additional
constitutional questions, as noted below.
1. Constitutional Issues Raised by the Junior/Senior Justice Proposal: The Good Behavior
and Appointments Clauses
Article III, Section 1 provides that: “The Judges, both of the supreme and inferior Courts,
shall hold their Offices during good Behaviour, and shall, at stated Times, receive for their
Services, a Compensation, which shall not be diminished during their Continuance in Office.”
59
The Appointments Clause of Article II, Section 2 provides that the President “shall nominate,
and by and with the Advice and Consent of the Senate, shall appoint Ambassadors, other public
Ministers and Consuls, Judges of the supreme Court, and all other Officers of the United States,
whose Appointments are not herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by
Law . . . .”
60
The issues raised under these constitutional provisions by any term limits statute are
complex, and what follows is a brief review of the relevant considerations. Commissioners
disagree about the proper resolution of the questions raised.
Those who believe that the Junior/Senior Justice proposal is unconstitutional start with
the Good Behavior Clause, which is conventionally interpreted to give federal judges “life
tenure”: Federal judges hold their offices for an indefinite period that ends only when they die,
voluntarily resign, or are involuntarily removed through the process of impeachment and
conviction. Although the Good Behavior Clause does not specify the details of the “offices” that
federal judges hold, the Appointments Clause arguably recognizes a separate office of “Judge[]
of the supreme Court” that is different from other federal judicial offices. If so, people who have
18
been appointed to the Supreme Court must remain “Judges of the supreme Court.” People who
believe that the Junior/Senior Justice proposal is unconstitutional argue that Senior Justices (who
would be barred from participating in the ordinary work of the Court after eighteen years) do not
remain “Judges of the supreme Court” in the sense that the Constitution requires. Indeed, given
the enormously consequential constitutional decisions of the Court that this Chapter emphasizes,
these critics argue it is implausible to claim that individual Justices can be involuntarily removed
from most of the Court’s constitutional work without being deemed to have lost their “office.” In
addition, some believe that these specific textual provisions should be understood in the context
of more general separation of powers principles, including the principle of judicial independence.
Part of the reason the Good Behavior and Appointments Clauses are best understood to deny
Congress the power to modify life tenure by statute, in this view, is to protect the structural
principle of judicial independence that underwrites Article III of the Constitution.
Proponents of the Junior/Senior Justice proposal believe that Congress may redefine the
office prospectively. Thus, for all new appointments made after the statute takes effect, the office
of Justice of the Supreme Court would mean serving as a Junior Justice for the first eighteen
years and serving as a Senior Justice thereafter. All Justices would have the same duties and
powers, but the nature of these duties would change over time. Under this approach, every
Justice, unless they retire, would eventually become a Senior Justice if they stay on the Court for
more than eighteen years. Note that under the terms of this argument, the statutory changes
would not apply to sitting Justices.
The debate hinges on the nature of the “office” of Justice of the Supreme Court that the
Constitution creates and whether a statute that contemplates that the Justices’ duties will change
after eighteen years removes them from that office in violation of the Good Behavior Clause.
Proponents, relying on the senior status statute, 28 U.S.C. § 371(b) and (e), conclude that a
change in duties does not necessarily involve a change in office because senior status judges still
hold their office. For the same reason, they believe that deciding cases is not essential to
continuing to hold office as a federal judge, and that deciding Supreme Court cases is not
essential to continuing to hold the office of a Supreme Court Justice.
In support of this conclusion, proponents argue that the Supreme Court approved this
system for senior judges in Booth v. United States.
61
In Booth, a unanimous Supreme Court held
that a lower court federal judge who retired under the predecessor of § 371(b) “remains in office”
within the meaning of Article III, Section 1.
62
The Court pointed out that senior judges exercise
the judicial power of the United States in deciding cases when designated to do so. “It is scarcely
necessary to say that a retired judge’s judicial acts would be illegal unless he who performed
them held the office of judge. It is a contradiction in terms to assert that one who has retired in
accordance with the statute may continue to function as a federal judge and yet not hold the
office of a judge.”
63
On one reading of Booth, a statutory change of duties does not remove a
judge from office as long as “[t]he purpose is . . . that he shall continue . . . to perform judicial
service.”
64
The Supreme Court reaffirmed this reasoning in 2003 in Nguyen v. United States.
65
Booth thus distinguishes between a change in duties, which is within the power of
Congress, and removal from office or reduction in compensation, which are not: “Congress may
lighten judicial duties, though it is without power to abolish the office or to diminish the
19
compensation appertaining to it.”
66
Moreover, those who believe statutory term limits are
constitutional argue that the reasoning of Booth and Nguyen also extends to retired Justices.
Retired Justices such as David Souter and Sandra Day O’Connor have often participated in
courts of appeals decisions pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 294. When they do, proponents of the
Junior/Senior Justice proposal believe they are best understood as having retained their office as
Supreme Court Justices because they are exercising federal power and they have not been
appointed to any new office. Hence, proponents conclude, Senior Justices retain the office of
Justice of the Supreme Court even if their duties have changed and no longer include
participation in the ordinary work of the Court. Critics, however, believe that retired Justices still
hold federal judicial office, which is required under Booth if they are to exercise federal judicial
power, but that they do not necessarily continue to occupy the constitutional office of Supreme
Court Justice.
67
Setting Booth aside, critics believe that the best understanding of the Constitution forbids
the change in duties that the Junior/Senior Justice proposal entails. One constitutional scholar
puts the argument this way: “To say there is a particular office of Supreme Court Justice, as
opposed to federal judge in general, is to say that the Constitution contemplates some connection
between the justices and the work of the Court.”
68
On one view, because the Court is a
decisionmaking body in which members participate and deliberate together, the ability to
“participat[e] in substantially all the body’s final decisions” is a necessary constitutional feature
of holding the office of “Judge[] of the supreme Court.”
69
Because the Junior/Senior Justice
proposal eliminates the right to participate in the Court’s decisions after eighteen years, some
think it marks a change in office that violates the Good Behavior Clause.
Critics have also discussed an alternative understanding of what it means to be a “Judge[]
of the supreme Court”: Instead of participating in substantially all of the Court’s final decisions,
perhaps each Justice must be able to participate in an equal share of the Court’s work. There is a
sense in which the Junior/Senior Justice proposal establishes equality among the Justices,
because each Justice has the same powers for the same period of time. But even so, critics argue
that “the proposal is not consistent with the Constitution’s idea of a term” (and with the
prevailing view that the Good Behaviour Clause prevents Congress from imposing
straightforward term limits).
70
In the critics’ view, Congress cannot establish a time limit after
which Justices lose the ability to participate equally in the Court’s decisions, even if all Justices
are subject to the same time limit.
To the extent that the proponents’ argument rests on the precedential authority of Booth,
critics believe that the precedent is limited. Booth involved the Compensation Clause of Article
III and the issue was whether Congress could cut the pay of lower federal court judges who had
voluntarily taken what we now call senior status. As permitted by a 1919 amendment to the
Judicial Code, they had chosen to “retire . . . from regular active service on the bench” but had
not “resign[ed] [their] office,”
71
and they continued to hear cases or perform other judicial duties.
The Court held that Congress could not constitutionally reduce their compensation because they
still remained in office and exercised federal judicial power. Thus, critics of statutory term limits
argue, Booth only holds that when judges voluntarily take senior status, but continue to hear
cases, Congress may not reduce their compensation under the Compensation Clause. According
20
to critics, it does not follow that Congress can require life-tenured Supreme Court Justices to
stop participating in the Supreme Court’s exercises of judicial power after eighteen years.
72
Proponents argue that if judges who have elected senior status “[c]ontinu[e] in Office”
within the meaning of the Compensation Clause, then a statute requiring judges to take senior
status after eighteen years would not deprive them of their “Offices” within the meaning of the
Good Behaviour Clause. In the proponents’ view, moreover, Booth and subsequent established
practice with respect to retired Justices foreclose the critics’ arguments about the essential nature
of the offices of “Judges of the supreme Court.” According to proponents, there is no meaningful
legal distinction between Supreme Court Justices and other federal judges as to whether they
retain their judicial office after Senior status, and whether or not that status is voluntarily chosen
or imposed by statute. On this view, substantial participation or equal participation in all merits
decisions is therefore not “inherent” in the nature of the office of Supreme Court Justice. The
critics’ assertion to the contrary, proponents argue, is belied by practice.
Critics respond that practice does not support allowing Congress to mandate a reduction
in duties after a certain number of years. And the fact that our current practices make a
reasonable accommodation for voluntary decisions does not mean that those practices establish a
general principle that extends to a new set of arrangements in which Justices have no say in the
matter.
Indeed, critics believe that the argument from history favors their position. Throughout
most of American history, members of Congress have assumed that the only constitutional way
to achieve term limits for Supreme Court Justices is through constitutional amendment. Starting
as early as 1807,
73
and continuing to the present, more than two hundred proposals have been
introduced in Congress to amend the Constitution to establish term limits for Supreme Court
Justices or for federal judges more generallysometimes in conjunction with other changes,
sometimes as a stand-alone measure. But the first bill to establish the functional equivalent of
term limits by statute was not introduced until 2020.
74
The very idea of mandating term limits by
statute is a recent innovation.
B. An Alternative Proposal: Original/Appellate Jurisdiction
An alternative to the Junior/Senior Justice proposal is the Original/Appellate Jurisdiction
proposal, under which all Justices continue to hear original jurisdiction cases throughout their
tenure in office, but only the nine most junior Justices in service hear cases brought to the Court
under its appellate jurisdiction.
75
The Court hears only a small number of cases through original
jurisdiction every year. Most cases, and almost all of the controversial cases, come before the
Court through its discretionary appellate jurisdiction. In addition to participating in cases
involving original jurisdiction, Senior Justices may also perform other duties, as in the
Junior/Senior Justice proposal above or under the current retirement statute. This proposal does
not separate appellate jurisdiction cases for reasons of efficiency. Rather, the proposal offers
another way of creating the effective equivalent of term limits that might avoid some of the
constitutional problems of the main proposal.
21
The central argument for the Original/Appellate proposal is that it can be linked to a
specific textual provision in the Constitution. Article III, Section 2 of the Constitution gives
Congress the power to regulate the Court’s appellate jurisdiction: “[T]he supreme Court shall
have appellate Jurisdiction, both as to Law and Fact, with such Exceptions, and under such
Regulations as the Congress shall make.”
76
In Marbury v. Madison,
77
the Court held that the
Exceptions and Regulations Clause applied only to the Court’s appellate jurisdiction and that
Congress could not alter the Court’s original jurisdiction.
78
The proposal argues, accordingly,
that although Congress must allow all Justices to hear all cases arising out of original
jurisdiction, it may provide, as a regulation of appellate jurisdiction, that only Junior Justices
hear appeals.
Although this proposal invokes a different congressional power, it raises some of the
same constitutional issues discussed above. No matter which enumerated power Congress is
exercising, Congress’s statutes must comport with the Good Behaviour Clause and the
Appointments Clause. If critics are correct that everyone who holds the office of “Judge[] of the
supreme Court” must be able to participate in substantially all of the Court’s final decisions, or
must remain eligible to participate in an equal share of the Court’s work, then the
Original/Appellate proposal would be vulnerable to the same objections as the Junior/Senior
Justice proposal.
Critics may raise several additional objections. First, critics will argue that the Exceptions
and Regulations Clause gives Congress the power to change the scope of the Supreme Court’s
appellate jurisdiction, but not the personnel who decide appeals. Put another way, the Clause
allows Congress to decide what appeals the Court can hear, but not who hears the appeals.
Proponents, in turn, will argue this does not attend to the distinction between
“exceptions” to and “regulations” of appellate jurisdiction that appears in the text of Article III.
“Exceptions” to appellate jurisdiction involve limiting what cases the Court may hear. But
“regulations” of appellate jurisdiction may also include deciding how the Court hears appeals
and who hears them. The Supreme Court has never addressed this precise issue.
A second objection is that the Original/Appellate proposal creates two panels. One panel,
consisting of all of the Justices, hears original jurisdiction cases. The other, consisting only of the
nine Justices most junior in service, hears appellate cases. As we discuss in Chapter 2 at greater
length, there is an argument that this aspect of the proposal would violate the provision in Article
III, Section 1 that “[t]he judicial Power of the United States, shall be vested in one supreme
Court.”
79
From a textual point of view, if there is “one” Supreme Court, then perhaps the Justices
must participate together in deciding merits cases and may not decide cases in separate panels.
A third objection to the Original/Appellate proposal is that, like all other proposals for
Supreme Court panels, it gives Congress too much power to gerrymander the Justices by subject
matter to attempt to manipulate the outcome of particular cases. If Congress may divide cases in
this way, why not in other ways that would undermine the Court’s integrity and independence?
For example, Congress might create a special panel that heard only cases involving abortion or
the environment.
22
Proponents might respond that whether or not a general power to divide the Court into
panels poses dangers, the Constitution itself creates a distinction between the Supreme Court’s
original and appellate jurisdiction. This provision offers a bright-line rule, which, according to
Marbury v. Madison, Congress may not vary. When Congress follows this bright-line rule, there
is no danger to judicial independence. Congress cannot expand or contract the Court’s original
jurisdiction. Therefore, the proposal does not assume that Congress has a general power to create
panels of the Court. It simply argues that this one, which matches distinctions already present in
the text of Article III, is constitutionally valid.
C. An Alternative Proposal: Designated Supreme Court Justices
The third proposal attempts to respond to the concern that the Junior/Senior Justice
proposal effectively removes Justices from their offices. Instead, it proposes that Presidents
henceforth only appoint judges from the lower federal courts to sit by designation on the
Supreme Court for a non-renewable term of eighteen years. The relevant statute will specify that
one of the duties of lower federal court judges (or some statutorily demarcated subset of these
judges) is that they may be called upon to serve by designation on the Supreme Court for
eighteen years, after which they would return to their original court.
80
Under this proposal, Presidents would no longer appoint anyone to the office of “Judge[]
of the supreme Court.” Instead, Presidents would simply designate lower court judges to serve on
the Court temporarily. The statute could provide that the designation is subject to the ordinary
advice and consent process. If the designation does not amount to appointment to a different
office (see the discussion below), advice and consent would not be required by the Constitution,
but Congress might nevertheless provide for it.
One main objection to the Designated Justices proposal is a textual argument. As noted
previously, the Appointments Clause of Article II contemplates a separate office of “Judge[] of
the supreme Court.” Therefore, critics will assert that the judges who sit and decide cases on the
Supreme Court must hold the office of “Judges of the supreme Court.”
Proponents will respond that the existence of a separate office of “Judge of the Supreme
Court” does not mean that someone not appointed to that office is forbidden to serve on the
Supreme Court by designation. Federal judges often serve on different courts by designation
without receiving new commissions. Retired Supreme Court Justices serve on appellate and
district courts; appellate judges serve as district judges, and district judges serve as appellate
judges by designation. In addition, Supreme Court seats have been filled on a temporary basis
through recess appointments without a lifetime appointment, and even without Senate
confirmation. The Vacancies Clause of Article II, Section 2, Clause 3, which applies to federal
offices generally, provides that “[t]he President shall have Power to fill up all Vacancies that
may happen during the Recess of the Senate, by granting Commissions which shall expire at the
End of their next Session.”
81
Over three hundred federal judges, including fifteen Supreme Court
Justices, have been appointed through this process.
82
Lower federal courts have approved of its
constitutionality.
83
If Presidents may temporarily fill Supreme Court vacancies without the
Senate’s advice and consent, the argument goes, a fortiori they should be permitted to do so with
the Senate’s advice and consent.
84
23
Critics will say that the Constitution distinguishes the Supreme Court from other federal
courts and that everyone who sits on the Supreme Court must hold the office of “Judge[] of the
supreme Court” (whether pursuant to a regular appointment under the Appointments Clause,
which lasts during good behavior, or a recess appointment under the Vacancies Clause, which
lasts for at most two years). Critics may also note that in the vast majority of cases, when a
President has made recess appointments to either the lower courts or the Supreme Court,
Congress has subsequently confirmed these judges and Justices to lifetime appointments.
85
And
when judges sit by designation on other courts, they usually remain only for a short time, and
sometimes only for a single case. This practice, critics of this proposal will argue, is very
different than a statutory designation lasting eighteen years, which would cover a sizeable
proportion—and often a majority—of any federal judge’s career. There is nothing temporary
about such appointments, and hence they cannot be justified by existing practice.
A second main objection to the Designated Justices proposal is rooted in past practice:
No person who does not hold the office of Justice of the Supreme Court has ever sat on or
decided a case before the Supreme Court.
86
Justices have indeed sat on lower federal courts from
the beginning of the Republic, and Justices who take senior status sit by designation today.
Nevertheless, the opposite has never occurred—lower federal court judges have never sat by
designation on the Supreme Court. The novelty of the practice suggests that it is unconstitutional.
Proponents will respond that if Justices may “move down” and sit on lower courts by
designation, there is no reason why lower court judges may not “move up” by designation. In
fact, district court judges often sit by designation on circuit courts of appeals. Proponents would
assert, therefore, that district and circuit court judges should also be able to sit by designation on
the Supreme Court. The novelty of a practice does not by itself prove that it is unconstitutional;
otherwise, a host of federal laws that exercised constitutional powers in new ways would be
unconstitutional.
87
V. Addressing the Risk of Repeated Confirmation Impasse
It is essential that any term limits proposal provide an acceptable mechanism for
resolving the problem of repeated confirmation impasses. Absent such a mechanism, the
repeated failure of the Senate to confirm any nominee would undermine a major justification for
staggered term limits: that each President be entitled to the same number of regular nominations.
Designing a structure to address the risk of impasse, however, is not an easy matter. That
structure must not give too much effective power to the President but also address the risk of
repeated confirmation impasses. And the difficulty of reforming the confirmation process is
among the reasons opponents of term limits reject the reform.
Reform of the general structure of presidential nomination and Senate confirmation is not
squarely within the Commission’s remit. In this Part we consider some means by which to
address potential confirmation impasses under a system of term limits. In addition, in an
Appendix to this Report we summarize some helpful testimony regarding potential reforms to
the confirmation process more generally.
24
A. Term Limits by Constitutional Amendment and the Confirmation Process
The options for designing a mechanism to avoid a confirmation impasse are different and
broader in the context of designing an amendment as opposed to a statute. Some have suggested
that a constitutional amendment should provide that a nominee will be deemed confirmed if the
Senate does not vote to disapprove within a specified time, such as four months after
nomination
88
(This proposal is somewhat similar to Madison’s initial proposal at the
Constitutional Convention that judges be deemed confirmed if they were not rejected by a two-
thirds vote of the Senate by a date certain, a proposal that the Convention rejected
89
). This might
be a good idea as a starting point, but more is required to address the risk of the Senate
repeatedly voting down successive nominees for a particular eighteen-year seat.
To begin to address this potential concern, the amendment would first have to define the
circumstances that trigger any fallback mechanism. For instance, the trigger might be the Senate
voting down two consecutive nominees. This trigger may be particularly apt if the amendment
also adopts the provision deeming a nominee automatically confirmed if the Senate fails to vote
at all after a set time. If that time is set at four months, then this fallback mechanism would come
into play after roughly eight months of a confirmation impasse. Another option would be to
trigger the fallback mechanism at a set amount of time after the date the President nominates a
person for the particular eighteen-year position.
The Commission is not aware of any scholarship that explores in-depth the issue of an
appropriate design for a fallback mechanism. Witnesses offered a few brief suggestions. One is
that the President present three nominees to the Senate; if the Senate rejects all three, the President
is then empowered to choose one of those to sit on the Court.
90
But Presidents could easily game
this system, choosing two figures the Senate would never approve and thereby effectively gaining
unilateral power to fill the seat. Another possibility would be for the amendment to specify that
the Senate cannot conduct other business while a nomination is pending.
91
But this approach would
preclude the Senate from acting on any number of urgent issues that might arise, including those
involving our national security.
From an institutional-design perspective, the challenge is that any backup mechanism that
stays within the traditional President-Senate framework risks giving either too much unilateral
power to the President or too much blocking power to the Senate. The solution might need to rest
with an institution that sits outside this framework. One possibility is that, in case of a prolonged
impasse, the chief judges of the twelve non-specialized federal courts of appeals (or a subset of
them) could be assigned one of two roles.
92
On one approach, once this fallback mechanism is
triggered, this body of chief judges would become the confirmation body for the President’s
choice. Two institutions of the government would thus still be required to confirm a Justice. A
subsidiary issue to consider is whether the President should be precluded from nominating any
individual whose appointment to the Court the Senate has affirmatively rejected.
A second option would be to give the chief judges (or a subset of them) the power to
directly designate a Justice after a prolonged impasse. The amendment could also limit the chief
25
judges to selecting a sitting federal court of appeals judge. These are the individuals with
appropriate experience whose fitness for the Court the chief judges would be in the best position
to evaluate. Good reasons might exist to appoint to the Court persons other than federal court of
appeals judges. But empowering the chief judges to directly appoint anyone in the country to the
Court would put enormous discretion in the hands of this body. Limiting the set of potential
appointees to existing court of appeals judges would substantially constrain this power. Because
this fallback mechanism would come into play only when the Senate repeatedly rejects a
President’s nominees, it is not likely to affect the majority of seats on the Court.
If one worries that the knowledge of the sitting chief judges’ identities would shape the
actions of the President or the Senate, this power could be given to a random selection of seven
or five of the chief judges. An advantage of using the chief judges (or a subset of them) is that
the amendment would not have to design from scratch a new, independent institution to serve as
the fallback mechanism. Given the complexities of designing such a new institution, as well as
questions about how well the public would accept that institution, the easier course may be to use
a set of actors who have been Senate confirmed already and for whom a selection mechanism
also already exists.
93
An amendment could instead provide that if the Senate rejected one nominee, the threshold
for confirmation of the next nominee for that seat would decrease. Alternatively, the amendment
could provide that if the Senate fails to confirm a nominee by a certain point, the President would
have the power to designate any sitting federal judge (or any circuit judge) to fill that eighteen-
year seat. But both of these options might be thought to give too much power to the President.
B. Term Limits by Statute and the Confirmation Process
If term limits are implemented by a statute rather than a constitutional amendment,
modifications to the confirmation process must be consistent with the current constitutional
framework, which gives the President the power to select a nominee and the Senate the power to
approve or disapprove. It might still be possible to create a backup mechanism of the sort
discussed above, but such a mechanism would have to be understood as a delegation of authority
by the Senate and/or the President. The constitutionality of such a delegation is not clear, and the
relevant actor might also be able to revoke it unilaterally, undoing most of its benefits.
It might also be possible to deal with the possibility of a prolonged impasse within the
existing constitutional framework. For instance, a statute might prescribe that the threshold for
confirmation decreases each time the Senate refuses to confirm a nominee. The constitutionality
of such a statute is unclear, however, given that the Constitution gives each chamber the power
over its own rules and procedures.
94
The Senate could instead incorporate such a policy into its
own Senate rules; a later Senate, however, could change that rule. Alternatively, consistent with
the Designated Justices proposal set out above, a statute might provide that in the event of an
impasse, the President could designate a lower court judge to fill the Supreme Court vacancy for
an eighteen-year term without Senate confirmation. This statute would be subject to many of the
same constitutional concerns as the Designated Justices proposal, although it would operate with
respect to only some seats rather than all of them.
26
Last, a statute might provide that if the Senate fails to confirm one or both of a
President’s scheduled appointments, the next President of a different party would lose a
corresponding number of appointments. While making party affiliation relevant to the operation
of the statute is problematic, this proposal does seem constitutional and reasonably effective, but
it poses the danger that an extended impasse would shrink the Court. Moreover, what is effected
by statute can also be undone by statute. This alternative thus could become another front in the
polarized and destabilizing partisan contestation of the times.
VI. Concluding Considerations
A final set of concerns about enacting term limits via statute rather than constitutional
amendment can be viewed as prudential or grounded in the separation of powers. If Congress has
the power to change the composition of the Court by statute, it could mean that Congress has
considerable flexibility in altering the duties of the Justices in other ways. Once Congress has
exercised the power to change the Court’s composition by statute in order to regularize
appointments, Congress might seek to do so for other purposes. If federal statutes can validly
restrict members of the Supreme Court to a very limited set of duties after a certain number of
years, Congress might try to establish other criteria for imposing similar limits on a subset of
Justices. Even if one focuses entirely on term limits, moreover, the group of Supreme Court
practitioners cited in the introduction to this Chapter warns that “a statutory solution would be
inherently unstable”; over the years, Congress might amend the system depending on whether
Congress and the White House are in the same hands at the moment.
95
Opponents of term limits
altogether are especially critical of a statutory approach, arguing that if term limits may be
changed by statute, then an angry Congress could punish the Court by reducing the term of office
anytime that the Congress chose to do so. Critics of the statutory approach argue that it is
precisely to avoid such risks that the Constitution does not permit Congress to impose term limits
by statute. On this view, the degree of consensus required for a constitutional amendment
provides important security against the composition of the Court being manipulated for partisan
or ideological reasons.
For some members of the Commission, the existence of constitutional doubt, as well as
the significance and complexity of adopting a system of term limits, are themselves reasons to
pursue the reform through constitutional amendment. They worry that a statute altering the
Court’s composition will generate greater uncertainty and mistrust than other constitutional
questions. When litigants eventually challenge a term limits statute, the Court would have to
decide on the constitutionality of a law that restructures the Court itself. There might also be
strong disagreements about which Justices should participate in the decision. No matter which
way the Court came out on the question, these Commissioners worry that the Court’s legitimacy,
or perceptions of its legitimacy, would be undermined.
Members of the Commission who support a statutory solution believe these concerns are
overblown. They do not believe that a term limits statute would be any more destabilizing than a
host of other issues that the Court has confronted over the years. They also think that inaction
carries its own risks, and that the appointments process now displays a degree of dysfunction that
27
makes remedial action urgent. Given the powers that Congress and the President already have to
regulate the Court, proponents believe that recognizing the power of Congress to regularize
appointments would not add more risk than it is worth—and as a practical matter, if the reform
were adopted with strong bipartisan support, the precedent established by the statute might not
carry over to other situations.
At a minimum, the contestability of statutory approaches counsels in favor of serious
deliberation by Congress if it chooses to consider this route. In these deliberations, we hope that
Congress would keep in mind the central structural values of our Constitution, particularly the
principle of judicial independence, and consider what future Congresses, armed with the same
constitutional powers, might someday attempt. Indeed, in recent years, we have seen democratic
governments “regress” or “backslide” with respect to judicial independence. This has come
about through electoral majorities using their power to restructure previously independent
institutions, including courts, to favor the political agendas of those governments. Comparative
political scientists have concluded that the democratic systems most resistant to this prospect are
those in which an electoral majority is not sufficient to change the fundamental structure of
institutions such as the courts.
1
Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 5 (July 16, 2021) (written testimony of the
Supreme Court Practitioners’ Committee), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/07/Geller-
Mahoney-Testimony.pdf.
2
See, e.g., Maggie Jo Buchanan, The Need for Supreme Court Term Limits, CTR. FOR AM. PROGRESS (Aug. 3,
2020), https://www.americanprogress.org/issues/courts/reports/2020/08/03/488518/need-supreme-court-term-limits;
Lee Drutman, It’s Time for Term Limits for Supreme Court justices, V
OX (June 27, 2018),
https://www.vox.com/platform/amp/polyarchy/2018/6/27/17511030/supreme-court-term-limits-retirement.
3
See, e.g., Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 2 (July 20, 2021) (written testimony
of Akhil Amar, Yale Law School), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/07/Amar-Testimony.pdf;
Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 6 (June 30, 2021) (written testimony of Michael
W. McConnell, Stanford Law School), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/06/McConnell-
SCOTUS-Commission-Testimony.pdf. One scholar who testified to the Commission, and had been against term
limits for the Court in the mid-2000s, now favored term limits and explained why her view had changed since then.
See Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 1-2 (July 20, 2021) (written testimony of
Vicki C. Jackson, Harvard Law School), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/07/Jackson-
Testimony.pdf (citing Vicki C. Jackson, Packages of Independence: The Selection and Tenure of Article III Judges,
95 G
EO. L.J. 965, 1007-08 (2007)).
4
Compare Robert P. George, Michael W. McConnell, Colleen A. Sheehan & Ilan Wurman, The Conservative
Constitution, N
ATL CONST. CTR. (2020),
28
https://constitutioncenter.org/media/files/The_Conservative_Constitution.pdf, with Caroline Fredrickson, Jamal
Greene & Melissa Murray, The Progressive Constitution, N
ATL CONST. CTR. (2020),
https://constitutioncenter.org/media/files/The_Progressive_Constitution.pdf.
5
See, e.g., J. Harvie Wilkinson III, Supreme Court Term Limits Wouldn't Solve Anything, WASH. POST (Oct. 17,
2021), https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2021/10/18/supreme-court-term-limits-wouldnt-solve-anything;
Stephen B. Burbank, Alternative Career Resolution II: Changing the Tenure of Supreme Court Justices, 154 U.
PA.
L. REV. 1511 (2006) (offering criticisms of the main reform proposals and the critiques of life tenure); Ward
Farnsworth, The Regulation of Turnover on the Supreme Court, 2005 U.
ILL. L. REV. 407 (2005) (defending the
system of life tenure); William G. Ross, The Hazards of Proposals to Limit the Tenure of Federal Judges and to
Permit Judicial Removal Without Impeachment, 35 V
ILL. L. REV. 1063 (1990); David R. Stras & Ryan W. Scott,
Retaining Life Tenure: The Case for a “Golden Parachute, 83 W
ASH. U. L.Q. 1397, 1397 (2005).
6
See State Supreme Courts, BALLOTPEDIA, https://ballotpedia.org/State_supreme_courts (detailing the election or
appointment procedure for each state); D.C. Code § 11-1502 (2021) (exemplifying a law with a mandatory
retirement age and renewable terms); Francis X. Shen, Aging Judges, 81 O
HIO STATE L.J. 235 app. (2020)
(providing mandatory retirement age data); C
OUNCIL OF STATE GOVTS, THE BOOK OF THE STATES 189 tbl.5.1
(2019) (furnishing term length data); Sandra Schultz Newman & Daniel Mark Isaacs, Historical Overview of the
Judicial Selection Process in the United States: Is the Electoral System in Pennsylvania Unjustified?, 49 V
ILL. L.
REV. 1 app. (2004) (providing state-by-state data on selection processes, term lengths, and retirement requirements).
7
See State Supreme Courts, supra note 6; D.C. CODE § 11-1502 (2021).
8
See State Supreme Courts, supra note 6.
9
See Jackson Testimony, supra note 3, at 1; Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 3
(June 25, 2021) (written testimony of Rosalind Dixon, University of New South Wales),
https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/06/Dixon-Letter-SC-commission-June-25-final.pdf (“[T]he
Justices continue to enjoy lifetime appointment, without being subject to any form of term limit or mandatory
retirement age, in ways that are increasingly unusual in global terms.”).
10
Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 3 (July 20, 2021) (written testimony of Tom
Ginsburg, University of Chicago Law School), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/07/Ginsburg-
Testimony.pdf.
11
Id. at 2.
12
U.S. CONST. art. III, § 1. This formula does not mean that judges, once in office, are entirely immune from
consequences or professional incentives. Judges may, of course, be impeached for high crimes and misdemeanors,
lower court judges may be elevated to higher courts, and Associate Justices may be appointed Chief Justice.
13
See Steven G. Calabresi & James Lindgren, Term Limits for the Supreme Court: Life Tenure Reconsidered, 29
H
ARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY 769, 778-79 (2006). Nevertheless, Supreme Court vacancies have always occurred
irregularly. See Allison Rabkin Golden, David Herman, Alexander Nocks, Ayoub Ouederni & Kaveri Sharma,
Vacancies and Tenures on the Supreme Court: A Response to Calabresi and Lindgren (2021) (on file with the
Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States).
14
Roger C. Cramton, Reforming the Supreme Court, 95 CALIF. L. REV. 1313, 1316-20 (2007).
15
Supreme Court Practitioners’ Committee Testimony, supra note 1, at 78-82; Justices 1789 to Present, SUP. CT.
U.S., https://www.supremecourt.gov/about/members_text.aspx.
16
David Ingold, Eighty Is the New 70 as Supreme Court Justices Serve Longer and Longer, BLOOMBERG (Apr. 7,
2017), https://www.bloomberg.com/graphics/2017-supreme-court-justice-tenure (“In 1900, justices tended to be in
their late 50s when they joined the court. Today, the average age is about five years younger, and President Donald
Trump’s nomination of Gorsuch, currently 49 years old, only furthers that trend.”); see also Presidential
Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 5 (June 30, 2021) (written testimony of Maya Sen, John F.
Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-
content/uploads/2021/06/Sen-Written-Testimony.pdf.
17
Both the median and modal number of appointments are 2, and the mean is 1.83. See Justices 1789 to Present,
supra note 15.
18
There have been only six if we include the Reconstruction period, in which Republicans, following Abraham
Lincoln’s assassination, refused to allow any appointments by his successor, Andrew Johnson.
29
19
See generally Terri L. Peretti, Promoting Equity in the Distribution of Supreme Court Appointments, in
R
EFORMING THE COURT: TERM LIMITS FOR SUPREME COURT JUSTICES 435 (Roger C. Cramton & Paul D. Carrington
eds., 2006).
20
Cf. Jason P. Davis & Kathleen M. Eisenhardt, Rotating Leadership and Collaborative Innovation: Recombination
Processes in Symbiotic Relationships, 56 A
DMIN. SCI. Q. 159, 194 (2011) (linking rotating personnel and innovation
in decisionmaking); Amir Erez, Jeffrey A. Lepine & Heather Elms, Effects of Rotated Leadership and Peer
Evaluation on the Functioning and Effectiveness of Self-Managed Teams: A Quasi-Experiment, 55 P
ERSONNEL
PSYCH. 929, 929 (2002) (“[T]eams that rotated leadership among members had higher levels of voice, cooperation,
and performance.”).
21
David Rock & Heidi Grant, Why Diverse Teams Are Smarter, HARV. BUS. REV. (Nov. 4, 2016),
https://hbr.org/2016/11/why-diverse-teams-are-smarter; Steven A. Ramirez, Diversity, Compliance, Ethics & In-
House Counsel, 48 U. T
OL. L. REV. 465, 483 (2017).
22
Darren Rosenblum & Yaron Nili, Board Diversity by Term Limits?, 71 ALA. L. REV. 211, 242-44 (2019)
(describing various businesses that have implemented term limits for members of their board of directors, and the
accompanying decline in the median age of members serving on these boards).
23
In Japan, for instance, judges are appointed by the Cabinet from lists of candidates nominated by the Supreme
Court and serve for a term of ten years. Courts in Japan, S
UP. CT. JAPAN (2020),
https://www.courts.go.jp/english/vc-files/courts-en/file/2020_Courts_in_Japan.pdf.
24
See Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States (July 16, 2021) (written testimony of
Margaret H. Marshall, Choate Hall & Stewart LLP), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-
content/uploads/2021/07/Marshall-Testimony.pdf.
25
Farnsworth, supra note 5, at 437-38.
26
See Burbank, supra note 5, at 1548; Arthur D. Hellman, Reining in the Supreme Court: Are Term Limits the
Answer?, in R
EFORMING THE COURT: TERM LIMITS FOR SUPREME COURT JUSTICES 291, 298-303 (Roger C. Cramton
& Paul D. Carrington eds., 2006).
27
See Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 12 (Oct. 2021) (written testimony of
Philip Bobbitt, Columbia Law School), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/10/Professor-Philip-
Bobbitt.pdf; Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the United States 5 (Aug. 2, 2021) (written
testimony of Michael Stokes Paulsen, University of St. Thomas School of Law),
https://www.regulations.gov/comment/PCSCOTUS-2021-0001-2159; Presidential Commission on the Supreme
Court of the United States 18 (July 20, 2021) (written testimony of Randy E. Barnett, Georgetown University Law
Center), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/07/Barnett-Testimony.pdf.
28
Farnsworth, supra note 5, at 411.
29
Empirical studies modeling the effects of term limits on doctrinal change suggest different possibilities. See Adam
Chilton, Daniel Epps, Kyle Rozema & Maya Sen, Designing Supreme Court Term Limits, 95
S. CAL. L. REV.
(forthcoming 2021) (manuscript at 40-42) (on file with the Presidential Commission on the Supreme Court of the
United States) (finding that all but one of the most prominent proposals for term limits would likely have produced
fewer flips than actually occurred in the real world); Christopher Sundby & Suzanna Sherry, Term Limits and
Turmoil: Roe v. Wade’s Whiplash, 98
TEX. L. REV. 121, 160 (2019) (concluding that “the danger of increased
instability due to term limits is very real” and needs to be weighed against the potential benefits of term limits); cf.
Stefanie A. Lindquist, Judicial Activism in State Supreme Courts: Institutional Design and Judicial Behavior, 28
S
TAN. L. & POLY REV. 61, 102 fig. 6 (2017) (indicating that the state supreme courts with either life tenure or
tenure until age 70 overrule fewer precedents than state supreme courts with most other judicial retention methods).
30
Cf. Farnsworth, supra note 5, at 416 (“A two-term president may reflect a single national mood, and there may be
value in a Court that cannot be remade by one such gust.”).
31
According to a committee of distinguished Supreme Court practitioners, however, “orchestrating timing within
two-year windows would still often prove difficult,” and “[t]he fact that more Justices would have shorter track
records” could also impede predictions. Supreme Court Practitioners’ Committee Testimony, supra note 1, at 86.
32
See Hellman, supra note 26, at 303-08.
33
Supreme Court Practitioners’ Committee Testimony, supra note 1, at 78-82; Justices 1789 to Present, supra note
15.
34
See Lee Epstein, Jack C. Knight & Olga Shvetsova, Comparing Judicial Selection Systems, 10 WM. & MARY BILL
RTS. J. 7, 36 (2001) (“Our analysis of non-renewable termsan institution used quite frequently in the European
30
contextsuggests . . . it may be more effective [than life tenure] at encouraging sincere behavior on the part of
justices.”); M
ICHAEL S. KANG & JOANNA M. SHEPHERD, FREE TO JUDGE? HOW CAMPAIGN FINANCE MONEY BIASES
JUDGES (Stanford Univ. Press, forthcoming 2023) (discussing the experience of state courts).
35
Farnsworth, supra note 5, at 411.
36
See Jackson Testimony, supra note 3, at 5; State Supreme Courts, supra note 6.
37
See Ginsburg Testimony, supra note 10, at 3; Zachary Elkins & Tom Ginsburg, Characteristics of National
Constitutions, Version 3.0, C
OMPAR. CONSTS. PROJECT (May 20, 2021),
https://comparativeconstitutionsproject.org/download-data/#.
38
Jackson Testimony, supra note 3, at 5.
39
See Justices 1789 to Present, supra note 15.
40
McConnell Testimony, supra note 3, at 7.
41
See Chilton, Epps, Rozema & Sen, supra note 29.
42
Tracey E. George & Chris Guthrie, Remaking the United States Supreme Court in the Courts’ of Appeals Image,
58 D
UKE L.J. 1439, 1461 (2009).
43
McConnell Testimony, supra note 3, at 5.
44
Id.
45
See Chapter 2, at 25; Segall, supra note X, at 656; Grove, supra note X.
46
Calabresi & Lindgren, supra note 13, at 826-31.
47
Chilton, Epps, Rozema & Sen, supra note 29, at 3.
48
Designers would have to consider how a term limits system would operate in relation to the existing set of
retirement statutes and whether those would need to be changed.
49
See Jackson Testimony, supra note 3, at 18.
50
See, e.g., Amar Testimony, supra note 3, at 3-4; Cramton, supra note 14, at 1323-25; H.R. 8424, 116th Cong.
(2020); H.R. 5140, 117th Cong. (2021); Term Limits, F
IX CT. (Sep. 29, 2020), https://fixthecourt.com/fix/term-
limits.
51
Amar Testimony, supra note 3.
52
510 U.S. 163 (1994).
53
28 U.S.C. § 43(b).
54
5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 299 (1803).
55
Id. at 309.
56
Id.
57
See generally Joshua Glick, Comment, On the Road: The Supreme Court and the History of Circuit Riding, 24
C
ARDOZO L. REV. 1753 (2003).
58
See 28 U.S.C. § 294.
59
U.S. CONST. art. III, § 1.
60
U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2.
61
291 U.S. 339 (1934).
62
Id. at 351.
63
Id. at 350.
64
Id.
65
539 U.S. 69, 72 (2003) (noting that while judges of the District Court for the Northern Mariana Islands cannot be
designated to sit on a federal court of appeals because they are not Article III judges, senior circuit judges “are, of
course, life-tenured Article III judges who serve during ‘good Behaviour’ for compensation that may not be
diminished while in office”).
66
Booth, 291 U.S. at 351.
67
In the alternative, one might argue that they retain judicial office, but not office as Supreme Court Justices, or that
they hold multiple judicial offices, and give up one when they take senior status. See David R. Stras & Ryan W.
Scott, Are Senior Judges Unconstitutional?, 92 C
ORNELL L. REV. 453, 475-78 (2007) (suggesting that both Booth
and 28 U.S.C. § 371 could be read to mean that senior status judges retain judicial office without still holding the
same offices that they served in before they retired); cf. William Baude, The Unconstitutionality of Justice Black, 98
T
EX. L. REV. 327, 338-42 (2019) (focusing specifically on the retirement of Supreme Court Justices, and discussing
the possibilities that they retain their old office, that they move into a new office, or that they started off with two
offices and surrender one upon retirement). But see the discussion infra.
31
68
John Harrison, The Power of Congress Over the Terms of Justices of the Supreme Court, in REFORMING THE
COURT: TERM LIMITS FOR SUPREME COURT JUSTICES 361, 366 (Roger C. Cramton & Paul D. Carrington eds., 2006).
69
Id.
70
Id. at 367; cf. Philip B. Kurland, The Constitution and the Tenure of Federal Judges: Some Notes from History, 36
U.
CHI. L. REV. 665, 697 (1969) (“I am quite convinced that it would be unconstitutional for the Congress to
attempt, by legislation, to establish a fixed term of office for judges of the federal constitutional courts.”).
71
Act of Feb. 25, 1919, ch. 29, § 6, 40 Stat. 1156, 1157 (codified as amended at 28 U.S.C. § 375 (1934)).
72
Because Booth involved the 1919 federal statute under which lower federal court judges had been deciding cases
as senior judges, Booth also concluded that it was “too late to contend that services so performed were extra-legal
and unconstitutional.Booth, 291 U.S. at 351. It is unclear what weight that factoror the practice of retired
Justices sitting by designation on lower federal courtswould carry in a statute that imposes for the first time on
Supreme Court Justices the new status of Senior Justices.
73
See 17 ANNALS OF CONG. 22 (1807).
74
See First-Ever Measure to End Life Tenure on the Supreme Court Via Statute, Not Amendment, To Be Introduced,
F
IX CT. (Sept. 29, 2020), https://fixthecourt.com/2020/09/first-ever-measure-end-life-tenure-supreme-court-via-
statute-not-amendment-introduced (referring to H.R. 8424, 116th Cong. (2020)).
75
See Jack M. Balkin, Don’t Pack the Court. Regularize Appointments., BALKINIZATION (Oct. 5, 2020),
https://balkin.blogspot.com/2020/10/dont-pack-court-regularize-appointments.html.
76
U.S. CONST. art. III, § 2.
77
5 U.S. 137 (1803).
78
Id. at 175.
79
U.S. CONST. art. III, § 1.
80
See Calabresi & Lindgren, supra note 13, at 855-58, 860 (2006) (considering the proposal but rejecting it because
the work of a Supreme Court Justice is not germane to the duties of a lower court judge).
81
U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2, cl. 3.
82
Diana Gribbon Motz, The Constitutionality and Advisability of Recess Appointments of Article III Judges, 97 VA.
L. REV. 1665, 1670 (2011).
83
See, e.g., United States v. Woodley, 751 F.2d 1008, 1014 (9
th
Cir. 1985) (stating that “a recess appointment to the
federal bench [] could exercise the judicial power of the United States”).
84
Following President Eisenhower’s recess appointments of three Justices, the Senate passed a resolution
discouraging the practice of Supreme Court recess appointments, but the primary concern there was that recess
appointments bypass the advice and consent process, not that they are temporary.
85
Motz, supra note 82, at 1670 (“By 2000, Presidents had made more than 300 recess appointments of Article III
judges, and of those, only thirty-four had not been confirmed.”).
86
Harrison, supra note 68, at 365.
87
A final objection to the Designated Justices proposal is that it adds new duties to the office of lower federal court
judge, perhaps triggering the germaneness analysis set out in Weiss v. United States, 510 U.S. 163 (1994), discussed
above. See Calabresi & Lindgren, supra 13, at 860 (2006) (raising this concern). This analysis might or might not
apply to judges appointed after the proposal’s enactmentWeiss assumes without deciding that germaneness also
governs the prospective addition of duties for unknown future officeholders.
88
McConnell Testimony, supra note 3, at 6.
89
Adam J. White, Toward the Framers' Understanding of Advice and Consent”: A Historical and Textual Inquiry,
29 H
ARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY 103 (2005).
90
Ginsburg Testimony, supra note 10, at 10.
91
See Steven G. Calabresi, End the Poisonous Process of Picking Supreme Court Justices, N.Y. TIMES (Sept. 22,
2020), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/09/22/opinion/ginsburg-supreme-court-confirmation.html (arguing that “the
Senate [should] be forbidden from taking action whatsoever on any of its calendars” in the event of “[f]ailure to
confirm a justice by July 1 of a president’s first or third year”).
92
Jackson Testimony, supra note 3, at 11 n.30.
93
The current federal statute that determines who serves as chief judge of a court of appeals, 28 U.S.C. § 45, is well-
designed and has served the country well. To the extent there is any concern Congress might modify the statute for
partisan reasons to game this fallback mechanism for Supreme Court appointments, the amendment could include
the provisions of the current statute.
32
94
U.S. CONST. art. I, § 5.
95
Supreme Court Practitioners’ Testimony, supra note 1, at 82; see also Harrison, supra note 68, at 372 (providing
examples of “gamesmanship” that could be attempted).